Thursday, January 11, 2024

Conundrum of Violence and Authoritarianism

 When I was a teenager, a friend of mine and I would play this video game that he had on his console. I do not know what the real name of the game was, but we called it the Fish Game. The rules were simple: you played as a fish swimming in a 2-dimensional aquarium. With you were smaller fish, which you could eat, and larger fish, which would eat you. As you consumed fish, you got bigger, and therefore higher up on the food chain.

Everything can be a lesson, if you are paying attention, and this game provided a lesson to me on the nature of violence: Nobody starts a fight that he thinks he will lose. Violence is therefore inherently predatory, with the initiator of the violence (the predator) under the assumption of assured victory, and the recipient (the prey) on the defensive.

The predator might have several weapons in his arsenal assure success, including greater strength, fighting technique, weapons, numbers, or even just the element of surprise. Whatever his weaponry, he estimates his chances of success to be near 100%. Whether or not he chooses to initiate violence also depends on how well he sizes up his prey. In the fish game it is clearly obvious who is bigger than whom, and the bigger fish always wins, because the only factor that determines the outcome of the struggle is the size. With humans, though, the outcome is less assured because the predator might make errors of judgement regarding the strength of his prey.

For example, let us imagine that the predator, a large muscular man with a knife seeks to end the life of a smaller man on a subway. Unbeknownst to the attacker, the prey has a concealed pistol. The predator instantly becomes the prey when the gun comes out, and the victory goes to the smaller man.

We tend to see these types of outcomes as a good thing, but we rarely ask ourselves why. Why is it that we want the smaller man to win? It is because the larger man initiated the violence, and so therefore assumes the role of the predator. Moreover, the only reason the predator initiated violence is because he thought he could do it without risk to himself. In other words, the predator esteems the suffering of his prey as less important than the thrill of victory, or the material rewards from a mugging. He lacks empathy, so the thought of victimizing someone else does not prevent him from acting on his violent impulse.

However, we could look at it another way. By concealing his weapon, the smaller man has allowed himself to be underestimated. In a sense, one might call this a form of deception, because all the cards were not on the table. The predator miscalculated and initiated violence based on a false assessment of the relative strengths and paid for it with his life. The question we must ask is whether this deception was justified. Is it morally acceptable to conceal one’s true capability for violence, deceiving all potential enemies into making the fatal mistake? Normally, we have a general repugnance for deceit, but in this case, it seems that deceit is not only acceptable but useful.

Why is deceit useful in this scenario? Because the predator was planning to attack before the attack occurred, so the predator is an invisible threat to anyone whom he perceives to be weaker. By acting as bait and luring the predator out into the open, he can be dispatched for the greater safety of the rest. However, we must then reconsider the labels of predator and prey, because if the “prey” is really lying in wait, hoping for someone to take the bait, then he is a type of ambush predator. While some people might find this sort of ambush predator to be morally repugnant, they should be reminded that he triggers violence only when a clear threat emerges from the crowd. As long as no one attacks him, there is no danger.

Another consideration, though, is that if the weaker man had openly carried the gun, no violence would have ensued, and peace would reign. This argument carries some merit because by openly carrying, the overall level of violence is reduced, and potential predators are kept in check. They might seethe with violent urges, but fear to act on them, and the fear thus keeps the peace. This is the effect of a highly visible police force, or an intimidating military presence.

However, it is a false peace, as the threat of violence is always lurking in the shadows, ready to pounce the moment the keeper of the peace’s guard is down. While violence is kept in check, the potential for violence is like a pot of rice on the stove, ready to boil over as soon as one’s back is turned. Is this kind of peace preferable to violence? It maybe the only real alternative.

The actual capability of the peacekeeping force is not as important as the appearance of power. It is the appearance of power, therefore, that keeps the peace. If the criminals are afraid to initiate violence because they believe in overwhelming force to be deployed in recompence, they will tremble in their boots, but stay their hands.

Finally, we come to the predicament of defending our oppressors. “We live in a society…” as the saying goes, but the structure of that society depends on the perception of powerful guardians of the peace. We might see them as oppressors, and maybe they are oppressors on some occasions (nobody is perfect). We might resent them for their perceived power over us, but if they leave us alone, we can live peacefully. Trouble brews, however, when we start to poke at these authorities. When we recognize and call out potential weaknesses in the peacekeepers, whether it is physical weakness, organization weakness, or moral uncertainty, we encourage the criminals, the predators, to take more liberties with our lives, and even though the actual strength of the police force has not changed, the perception of the police inefficacy creates an environment that invites crime, violence, and suffering.

While we might resent the authorities because we perceive them as weak or incompetent, it is vital for the safety of the community that the criminals perceive the authorities as omniscient and omnipotent. We must not help the criminals by weakening the perception of the police, regardless of how we personally feel about them. However, we should hold them to high moral, organization, and functional standards, regardless. We should encourage the illusion of a powerful police force, even if we personally see the cracks in the façade, as this façade is the thin blue line that separates civilization from anarchy.

If anarchy ensues, then we are back on the subway, and we are either the predator, the prey, or the ambush predator, and if our society is disarmed, then we are all just fish in an aquarium, where the big fish eat the smaller ones with impunity.